Yes, freedom of speech should be absolute
This fundamental liberty shouldn’t be killed with qualifications.
Want to read spiked ad-free? Become a spiked supporter.
Imagine if the Founding Fathers had conceived of liberty and freedom in contemporary terms, as problems to be managed, as sources of risk and harm. Imagine if Thomas Jefferson had penned the Declaration of Independence now, with the assertion that life, liberty and the pursuit of happiness were inalienable rights coupled with the get-out ‘except when said pursuit causes ill health’. Imagine if the American Constitution and, subsequently, the Bill of Rights had been drawn up today, complete with a set of sub-claused qualifications and caveats about offending people on grounds of race or religion. As for the First Amendment, so crystalline in its protection of free speech and press freedom, it just could not have been formulated today in the way that it was. ‘Congress’, it runs, ‘shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble, and to petition the Government for a redress of grievances.’
It doesn’t say ‘Congress shall make no law abridging freedom of speech except when a person uses threatening, abusive or insulting words likely to stir up hatred’. It doesn’t say ‘Congress shall make no law abridging freedom of speech except when it is necessary to protect health or morals, or the reputation or rights of others’. In short, it doesn’t contain caveats or exceptions. In the eyes of the Founding Fathers, people’s freedom to think what they choose to think, to believe what they choose to believe, and to say what they want to, was absolute – it brooked no compromise.
And why were there none of the exceptions, or the caveats, or the famous ‘limits’ to free speech that we’d no doubt find if a Bill of Rights was drawn up to today? Because, quite simply, freedom of thought and speech was seen as something too important to be bounded or qualified. It wasn’t that someone like Thomas Jefferson, or Tom Paine, or Voltaire, not to mention the many others who breathed in the radical, liberty-thirsting air of the time, were unaware of malicious speech, or abusive speech, or even just plain idiotic speech. Not everyone was dead smart during the Age of Enlightenment. It’s just that at that moment freedom, and free speech, was seen in its positive aspect, as something that benefitted humankind, a principle that prevented a government from slipping towards tyranny, that allowed the ‘better angels of our nature’ to flourish, that aided the pursuit of truth. See, for instance, Madison’s criticisms of the Alien and Sedition Acts in 1800 in which he drew on the First Amendment to defend the press’s right to be ‘seditious’, and made a case for ‘the intent to excite… unfavourable sentiments against those who administer the government’. For Madison, then, the freedom to lambast public figures, to excite others’ antagonism towards those figures – something that today would be classed as ‘incitement to hatred’ – was far more important than protecting those figures from emotional harm. The emphasis always fell on freedom of speech, and never its restriction.
Today, the Founding Fathers, and later the likes of John Stuart Mill, whose defence of free speech was, at points, equally as stalwart as his liberal predecessors across the pond, are implicitly assumed to have underestimated the harm in free speech. They were naive; they didn’t know what we know now; namely, that freedom of speech is never absolute, that there must be limits.
Just think of the number of people who proclaim their support for free speech before reeling off a list of reasons why its exercise must be limited. In the UK, for instance, the head of civil-liberties group Liberty, Shami Chakrabarti, is seemingly more concerned with the problems of free speech than its benefits – hence she once talked of ‘respecting freedom of conscience, thought and religion and free speech within such proportionate limits as are necessary to protect others’. Little wonder she ended up sat on the ‘panel of experts’ at the press-freedom-quashing Leveson Inquiry.
Or take an even more prominent example: article 10 of the European Convention on Human Rights. ‘Everyone has the right to freedom of expression’, it says, before stating that this freedom ‘may be subject to such formalities, conditions, restrictions or penalties as are prescribed by law and are necessary in a democratic society, in the interests of national security, territorial integrity or public safety, for the prevention of disorder or crime, for the protection of health or morals, for the protection of the reputation or rights of others, for preventing the disclosure of information received in confidence, or for maintaining the authority and impartiality of the judiciary’. Whatever this ‘fundamental right’ is, given the volume of restrictions on it, it is not freedom of speech in any true sense; rather, it’s speech within given limits.
Indeed, it’s very difficult to find anyone who will defend free speech as an absolute. Sure, virtually every figure in public life will say they support free speech, but that’s usually just a prelude to a statement saying why it must be limited.
Of course, if you defend freedom of speech absolutely, this does not mean defending the freedom to commit perjury, for instance. That’s an act which undermines the principles of a justice system and makes it unworkable – there is no freedom to lie under oath. Likewise, telling someone to kill someone, while pressing a gun into the palm of their hand, is not an act of free speech; it’s incitement to murder. Incredible as it might seem, it is possible to defend free speech absolutely without defending perjury or incitement to murder (clue: these are not issues of free speech). Hence the architects of the Bill or Rights felt no need to add in caveats to that effect – because neither they nor the citizens they represented were idiots.
But the majority of those who accompany their profession of support for free speech with a whole raft of anti-free-speech qualifications do so for subtler reasons. They emphasise the harm that speech can do. They talk, as one columnist did recently, of ‘issues of security and personal safety, of the value of truth and honesty, the need to treat others with respect’. Or, as another columnist did, they warn of the dangerous influence of certain speech: ‘The fractional loss of liberty entailed in penalising the expression of neo-Nazi views or Holocaust denial seems a small price to pay compared to what can follow if the far right is shielded all the way into power.’
What becomes clear is that all those who determinedly qualify freedom out of speech don’t really believe in free speech at all. They pose as reasonable and moderate. And they act as if their worries over unfettered free speech are born of a concern for others. But in reality, their problem is that they can only see freedom of speech in negative terms, as something that can cause harm or damage. Which is another way of saying that they see the freedom of other people, their freedom to think and speak for themselves, as a problem, as a source of potential harm. Their putative concern for the welfare of people, then, is really a profound mistrust of people – we’re not deemed capable of handling free speech, and the hustle and sometimes abusive bustle of public life. This is what sets the contemporary pseudo advocacy of free speech, complete with qualifications and caveats, apart from a real belief in free speech of the type that animated the authors of the First Amendment. The Founding Fathers had faith in people’s capacity to act and think for themselves; that is singularly absent today.
Tim Black is deputy editor of spiked.
To enquire about republishing spiked’s content, a right to reply or to request a correction, please contact the managing editor, Viv Regan.
Comments
Want to join the conversation?
Only spiked supporters and patrons, who donate regularly to us, can comment on our articles.